THE REPRODUCTION OF EVERYDAY LIFE
The everyday practical activity of tribesmen
reproduces, or perpetuates, a tribe. This reproduction is not merely physical,
but social as well. Through their daily activities the tribesmen do not merely
reproduce a group of human beings; they reproduce a tribe, namely a particular
social form within which this group of human beings performs specific activities
in a specific manner. The specific activities of the tribesmen are not the outcome
of "natural" characteristics of the men who perform them, the way the production
of honey is an outcome of the "nature" of a bee. The daily life enacted and
perpetuated by the tribesman is a specific social response to particular material
and historical conditions.
The everyday activity of slaves reproduces slavery. Through their daily activities,
slaves do not merely reproduce themselves and their masters physically; they
also reproduce the instruments with which the master represses them, and their
own habits of submission to the master's authority. To men who live in a slave
society, the master-slave relation seems like a natural and eternal relation.
However, men are not born masters or slaves. Slavery is a specific social form,
and men submit to it only in very particular material and historical conditions.
The practical everyday activity of wage-workers reproduces wage labor and capital.
Through their daily activities, "modern" men, like tribesmen and slaves, reproduce
the inhabitants, the social relations and the ideas of their society; they reproduce
the social form of daily life. Like the tribe and the slave system, the capitalist
system is neither the natural nor the final form of human society; like the
earlier social forms, capitalism is a specific response to material and historical
conditions.
Unlike earlier forms of social activity, everyday life in capitalist society
systematically transforms the material conditions to which capitalism originally
responded. Some of the material limits to human activity come gradually under
human control. At a high level of industrialization, practical activity creates
its own material conditions as well as its social form. Thus the subject of
analysis is not only how practical activity in capitalist society reproduces
capitalist society, but also how this activity itself eliminates the material
conditions to which capitalism is a response.
Daily Life in Capitalist Society
The social form of people's regular activities under capitalism is a response
to a certain material and historical situation. The material and historical
conditions explain the origin of the capitalist form, but do not explain why
this form continues after the initial situation disappears. A concept of "cultural
lag" is not an explanation of the continuity of a social form after the disappearance
of the initial conditions to which it responded. This concept is merely a name
for the continuity of the social form. When the concept of "cultural lag" parades
as a name for a "social force" which determines human activity, it is an obfuscation
which presents the outcome of people's activities as an external force beyond
their control. This is not only true of a concept like "cultural lag." Many
of the terms used by Marx to describe people's activities have been raised to
the status of external and even "natural" forces which determine people's activity;
thus concepts like "class struggle," "production relations" and particularly
"The Dialectic," play the same role in the theories of some "Marxists" that
"Original Sin," "Fate" and "The Hand of Destiny" played in the theories of medieval
mystifiers.
In the performance of their daily activities, the members of capitalist society
simultaneously carry out two processes: they reproduce the form of their activities,
and they eliminate the material conditions to which this form of activity initially
responded. But they do not know they carry out these processes; their own activities
are not transparent to them. They are under the illusion that their activities
are responses to natural conditions beyond their control and do not see that
they are themselves authors of those conditions. The task of capitalist ideology
is to maintain the veil which keeps people from seeing that their own activities
reproduce the form of their daily life; the task of critical theory is to unveil
the activities of daily life, to render them transparent, to make the reproduction
of the social form of capitalist activity visible within people's daily activities.
Under capitalism, daily life consists of related activities which reproduce
and expand the capitalist form of social activity. The sale of labor-time for
a price (a wage), the embodiment of labortime in commodities (saleable goods,
both tangible and intangible), the consumption of tangible and intangible commodities
(such as consumer goods and spectacles)-these activities which characterize
daily life under capitalism are not manifestations of "human nature," nor are
they imposed on men by forces beyond their control.
If it is held that man is "by nature" an uninventive tribesman and an inventive
businessman, a submissive slave and a proud craftsman an independent hunter
and a dependent wage-worker, then either man's "nature" is an empty concept,
or man's "nature'' depends on material and historical conditions, and is in
fact a response to those conditions.
Alienation of Living Activity
In capitalist society, creative activity takes the form of commodity production,
market production of marketable goods, and the results of human activity take
the form of commodities. Marketability or saleability is the universal characteristic
of all practical activity and all products. The products of human activity which
are necessary for survival have the form of saleable goods: they are only available
in exchange for money. And money is only available in exchange for commodities.
If a large number of men accept the legitimacy of these conventions, if they
accept the convention that commodities are a prerequisite for money, and that
money is a prerequisite for survival, then they find themselves locked into
a vicious circle. Since they have no commodities, their only exit from this
circle is to regard themselves, or parts of themselves, as commodities. And
this is, in fact, the peculiar "solution" which men impose on themselves in
the face of specific material and historical conditions. They do not exchange
their bodies or parts of their bodies for money. They exchange the creative
content of their lives, their practical daily activity, for money.
As soon as men accept money as an equivalent for life, the sale of living activity
becomes a condition for their physical and social survival. Life is exchanged
for survival. Creation and production come to mean sold activity. A man's activity
is "productive," useful to society, only when it is sold activity. And the man
himself is a productive member of society only if the activities of his daily
life are sold activities. As soon as people accept the terms of this exchange,
daily activity takes the form of universal prostitution.
The sold creative power, or sold daily activity, takes the form of labor. Labor
is a historically specific form of human activity. Labor is abstract activity
which has only one property: it is marketable, it can be sold for a given quantity
of money. Labor is indifferent activity: indifferent to the particular task
performed and indifferent to the particular subject to which the task is directed.
Digging, printing and carving are different activities, but all three are labor
in capitalist society. Labor is simply "earning money." Living activity which
takes the form of labor is a means to earn money. Life becomes a means of survival.
This ironic reversal is not the dramatic climax of an imaginative novel; it
is a fact of daily life in capitalist society. Survival, namely self-preservation
and reproduction, is not the means to creative practical activity, but precisely
the other way around. Creative activity in the form of labor, namely sold activity,
is a painful necessity for survival; labor is the means to selfpreservation
and reproduction.
The sale of living activity brings about another reversal. Through sale, the
labor of an individual becomes the "property" of another, it is appropriated
by another, it comes under the control of another. In other words, a person's
activity becomes the activity of another, the activity of its owner; it becomes
alien to the person who performs it. Thus one's life, the accomplishments of
an individual in the world, the difference which his life makes in the life
of humanity, are not only transformed into labor, a painful condition for survival;
they are transformed into alien activity, activity performed by the buyer of
that 1abor. In capitalist society, the architects, the engineers, the laborers,
are not builders; the man who buys their labor is the builder; their projects,
calculations and motions are alien to them; their living activity, their accomplishments,
are his.
Academic sociologists, who take the sale of labor for granted, understand this
alienation of labor as a feeling: the worker's activity "appears" alien to the
worker, it "seems" to be controlled by another. However, any worker can explain
to the academic sociologists that the alienation is neither a feeling nor an
idea in the worker's head, but a real fact about the worker's daily life. The
sold activity is in fact alien to the worker; his labor is in fact controlled
by its buyer.
In exchange for his sold activity, the worker gets money, the conventionally
accepted means of survival in capitalist society. With this money he can buy
commodities, things, but he cannot buy back his activity. This reveals a peculiar
"gap" in money as the "universal equivalent." A person can sell commodities
for money, and he can buy the same commodities with money. He can sell his living
activity for money, but he cannot buy his living activity for money.
The things the worker buys with his wages are first of all consumer goods which
enable him to survive, to reproduce his laborpower so as to be able to continue
selling it; and they are spectacles, objects for passive admiration. He consumes
and admires the products of human activity passively. He does not exist in the
world as an active agent who transforms it. but as a helpless impotent spectator
he may call this state of powerless admiration "happiness," and since labor
is painful, he may desire to be "happy," namely inactive, all his life (a condition
similar to being born dead). The commodities, the spectacles, consume him; he
uses up living energy in passive admiration; he is consumed by things. In this
sense, the more he has, the less he is. (An individual can surmount this death-in-life
through marginal creative activity; but the population cannot, except by abolishing
the capitalist form of practical activity, by abolishing wagelabor and thus
de-alienating creative activity.)
The Fetishism of Commodities
By alienating their activity and embodying it in commodities, in material receptacles
of human labor, people reproduce themselves and create Capital. From the standpoint
of capitalist ideology, and particularly of academic Economics, this statement
is untrue: commodities are "not the product of labor alone"; they are produced
by the primordial "factors of production," Land, Labor and Capital, the capitalist
Holy Trinity, and the main "factor" is obviously the hero of the piece, Capital.
The purpose of this superficial Trinity is not analysis, since analysis is not
what these Experts are paid for. They are paid to obfuscate, to mask the social
form of practical activity under capitalism, to veil the fact that producers
reproduce themselves, their exploiters, as well as the instruments with which
they're exploited. The Trinity formula does not succeed in convincing. It is
obvious that land is no more of a commodity producer than water, air, or the
sun. Furthermore Capital, which is at once a name for a social relation between
workers and capitalists, for the instruments of production owned by a capitalist,
and for the money-equivalent of his instruments and "intangibles," does not
produce anything more than the ejaculations shaped into publishable form by
the academic Economists. Even the instruments of production which are the capital
of one capitalist are primordial "factors of production" only if one's blinders
limit his view to an isolated capitalist firm, since a view of the entire economy
reveals that the capital of one capitalist is the material receptacle of the
labor alienated to another capitalist. However, though the Trinity formula does
not convince, it does accomplish the task of obfuscation by shifting the subject
of the question: instead of asking why the activity of people under capitalism
takes the form of wage-labor, potential analysts of capitalist daily life are
transformed into academic house-Marxists who ask whether or not labor is the
only "factor of production."
Thus Economics (and capitalist ideology in general) treats land, money, and
the products of labor, as things which have the power to produce, to create
value, to work for their owners, to transform the world. This is what Marx called
the fetishism which characterizes people's everyday conceptions, and which is
raised to the level of dogma by Economics. For the economist, living people
are things ("factors of production"), and things live (money "works," Capital
"produces"). The fetish worshipper attributes the product of his own activity
to his fetish. As a result, he ceases to exert his own Fewer (the power to transform
nature, the power to determine the form and content of his daily life); he exerts
only those "powers" which he attributes to his fetish (the "power" to buy commodities).
In other words, the fetish worshipper emasculates himself and attributes virility
to his fetish.
But the fetish is a dead thing, not a living being; it has no virility. The
fetish is no more than a thing for which, and through which, capitalist relations
are maintained. The mysterious power of Capital, its "power" to produce, its
virility, does not reside in itself, but in the fact that people alienate their
creative activity, that they sell their labor to capitalists, that they materialize
or reify their alienated labor in commodities. In other words, people are bought
with the products of their own activity, yet they sec their own activity as
the activity of Capital, and their own products as the products of Capital.
By attributing creative power to Capital and not to their own activity, they
renounce their living activity, their everyday life, to Capital, which means
that people give themselves daily, to the personification of Capital, the capitalist.
By selling their labor, by alienating their activity, people daily reproduce
the personifications of the dominant forms of activity under capitalism, they
reproduce the wage-laborer and the capitalist. They do not merely reproduce
the individuals physically, but socially as well; they reproduce individuals
who are sellers of labor-power, and individuals who are owners of means of production;
they reproduce the individuals as well as the specific activities, the sale
as well as the ownership.
Every time people perform an activity they have not themselves defined and do
not control, every time they pay for goods they produced with money they received
in exchange for their alienated activity, every time they passively admire the
products of their own activity as alien objects procured by their money, they
give new life to Capital and annihilate their own lives.
The aim of the process is the reproduction of the relation between the worker
and the capitalist. However, this is not the aim of the individual agents engaged
in it. Their activities are not transparent to them; their eyes are fixed on
the fetish that stands between the act and its result. The individual agents
keep their eyes fixed on things, precisely those things for which capitalist
relations are established. The worker as producer aims to exchange his daily
labor for money-wages, he aims precisely for the thing through which his relation
to the capitalist is re established, the thing through which he reproduces himself
as a wage- worker and the other as a capitalist. The worker as consumer exchanges
his money for products of labor, precisely the things which the capitalist has
to sell in order to realize his Capital.
The daily transformation of living activity into Capital is mediated by things,
it is not carried out by the things. The fetish worshipper does not know this;
for him labor and land, instruments and money, entrepreneurs rind bankers, are
all "factors" and "agents." When a hunter wearing an amulet downs a deer with
a stone, he may consider the amulet an essential "factor" in downing the deer
and even in providing the deer as an object to be downed. If he is a responsible
and well-educated fetish worshipper, he will devote his attention to his amulet,
nourishing it with care and admiration; in order to improve the material conditions
of his life, he will improve the way he wears his fetish, not the way he throws
the stone; in a bind, he may even send his amulet to "hunt" for him. His own
daily activities are not transparent to him: when he eats well, he fails to
see that it is his own action of throwing the stone, and not the action of the
amulet, that provided his food; when he starves, he fails to See that it is
his own action of worshipping the amulet instead of hunting, and not the wrath
of his fetish, that causes his starvation.
The fetishism of commodities and money, the mystification of one's daily activities,
the religion of everyday life which attributes living activity to inanimate
things, is not a mental caprice born in men's imaginations; it has its origin
in the character of social relations under capitalism. Men do in fact relate
to each other through things; the fetish is in fact the occasion for which they
act collectively, and through which they reproduce their activity. But it is
not the fetish that performs the activity. It is not Capital that transforms
raw materials, nor Capital that produces goods. If living activity did not transform
the materials, these would remain untransformed, inert, dead matter. If men
were not disposed to continue selling their living activity, the impotence of
Capital would be revealed; Capital would cease to exist; its last remaining
potency would be the power to remind people of a bypassed form of everyday life
characterized by daily universal prostitution.
The worker alienates his life in order to preserve his life. If he did not sell
his living activity he could not get a wage and could not survive. However,
it is not the wage that makes alienation the condition for survival. If men
were collectively not disposed to sell their lives, if they were disposed to
take control over their own activities, universal prostitution would not be
a condition for survival. It is people's disposition to continue selling their
labor, and not the things for which they sell it, that makes the alienation
of living activity necessary for the preservation of life.
The living activity sold by the worker is bought by the capitalist. And it is
only this living activity that breathes life into Capital and makes it "productive."
The capitalist, an "owner" of raw materials and instruments of production, presents
natural objects and products of other people's labor as his own "private property.
But it is not the mysterious power of Capital that creates the capitalist's
"private property" ;living activity is what creates the "property," and the
form of that activity is what keeps it "private."
Transformation of Living Activity into Capital
The transformation of living activity into Capital takes place through things,
daily, but is not carried out by things. Things which are products of human
activity seem to be active agents because activities and contacts are established
for and through things, and because people's activities are not transparent
to them; they confuse the mediating object with the cause.
In the capitalist process of production, the worker embodies or materializes
his alienated living energy in an inert object by using instruments which are
embodiments of other people's activity. (Sophisticated industrial instruments
embody the intellectual and manual activity of countless generations of inventors,
improvers and producers from all corners of the globe and from varied forms
of society.) The instruments in themselves are inert objects; they are material
embodiments of living activity, but are not themselves alive. The only active
agent in the production process is the living laborer. He uses the products
of other people's labor and infuses them with life, so to speak, but the life
is his own; he is not able to resurrect the individuals who stored their living
activity in his instrument. The instrument may enable him to do more during
a given time period, and in this sense it may raise his productivity. But only
the living labor which is able to produce can be productive.
For example, when an industrial worker runs an electric lathe, he uses products
of the labor of generations of physicists, inventors, electrical engineers,
lathe makers. He is obviously more productive than a craftsman who carves the
same object by hand. But it is in no sense the "Capital" at the disposal of
the industrial worker which is more "productive" than the "Capital'' of the
craftsman. If generations of intellectual and manual activity had not been embodied
in the electric lathe, if the industrial worker had to invent the lathe, electricity,
and the electric lathe, then it would take him numerous lifetimes to turn a
single object on an electric lathe, and no amount of Capital could raise his
productivity above that of the craftsman who carves the object by hand.
The notion of the "productivity of capital," and particularly the detailed measurement
of that "productivity," are inventions of the "science" of Economics, that religion
of capitalist daily life which uses up people's energy in the worship, admiration
and flattery of the central fetish of capitalist society. Medieval colleagues
of these "scientists" performed detailed measurements of the height and width
of angels in Heaven, without ever asking what angels or Heaven were, and taking
for granted the existence of both.
The result of the worker's sold activity is a product which does not belong
to him. This product is an embodiment of his labor, a materialization of a part
of his life, a receptacle which contains his living activity, but it is not
his; it is: as alien to him as his labor. He did not decide to make it, and
when it is made he does not dispose of it. If he wants it, he has to buy it.
What he has made is not simply a product with certain useful properties; for
that he did not need to sell his labor to a capitalist in exchange for a wage;
he need only have picked the necessary materials and the available tools, he
need only have shaped the materials guided by his goals and limited by his knowledge
and ability. (It is obvious that an individual can only do this marginally;
men's appropriation and use of the materials and tools available to them can
only take place after the overthrow of the capitalist form of activity.)
What the worker produces under capitalist conditions is a product with a very
specific property, the property of saleability. What his alienated activity
produces is a commodity.
Because capitalist production is commodity production, the statement that the
goal of the process is the satisfaction of human needs is false; it is a rationalization
and an apology. The "satisfaction of human needs" is not the goal of the capitalist
or of the worker engaged in production, nor is it a result of the process. The
worker sells his labor in order to get a wage; the specific content of the labor
is indifferent to him; he does not alienate his labor to a capitalist who does
not give him a wage in exchange for it, no matter how many human needs this
capitalist's products may satisfy. The capitalist buys labor and engages it
in production in order to emerge with commodities which can be sold. He is indifferent
to the specific properties of the product, just as he is indifferent to people's
needs; all that interests him about the product is how much it will sell for,
and all that interests him about people's needs is how much they "need" to buy
and how they can be coerced, through propaganda and psychological conditioning,
to "need" more. The capitalist's goal Is to satisfy his need to reproduce and
enlarge Capital, and the result of the process is the expanded reproduction
of wage labor and Capital (which are not "human needs").
The commodity produced by the worker is exchanged by the capitalist for a specific
quantity of money; the commodity is a value which is exchanged for an equivalent
value. In other words, the living and past labor materialized in the product
can exist in two distinct yet equivalent forms, in commodities and in money,
or in what is common to both, value. This does not mean that value is labor.
Value is the social form of reified (materialized) labor in capitalist society.
Under capitalism, social relations are not established directly; they are established
through value. Everyday activity is not exchanged directly; it is exchanged
In the form of value. Consequently, what happens to living activity under capitalism
cannot be traced by observing the activity itself, but only by following the
metamorphoses of value.
When the living activity of people takes the form of labor (alienated activity),
it acquires the property of exchangeability; it acquires the form of value.
In other words, the labor can be exchanged for an "equivalent" quantity of money
(wages). The deliberate alienation of living activity, which is perceived as
necessary for survival by the members of capitalist society, itself reproduces
the capitalist form within which alienation is necessary for survival. Because
of the fact that living activity has the form of value, the products of that
activity must also have the form of value: they must be exchangeable for money.
This is obvious since, if the products of labor did not take the form of value,
but for example the form of useful objects at the disposal of society, then
they would either remain in the factory or they would be taken freely by the
members of society whenever a need for them arose; in either case, the money-wages
received by the workers would have no value, and living activity could not be
sold for an "equivalent" quantity of money; living activity could not be alienated.
Consequently, as soon as living activity takes the form of value, the products
of that activity take the form of value, and the reproduction of everyday life
takes place through changes or metamorphoses of value.
The capitalist sells the products of labor on a market; he exchanges them for
an equivalent sum of money; he realizes a determined value. The specific magnitude
of this value on a particular market is the price of the commodities. For the
academic Economist, Price is St. Peter's key to the gates of Heaven. Like Capital
itself, Price moves within a wonderful world which consists entirely of objects;
the objects have human relations with each other, and are alive; they transform
each other, communicate with each other; they marry and have children. .nd of
course it is only through the grace of these intelligent, powerful and creative
objects that people can be so happy in capitalist society.
In the Economist's pictorial representations of the workings of heaven, the
angels do everything and men do nothing at all; men simply enjoy what these
superior beings do for them. Not only does Capital produce and money work; other
mysterious beings have similar virtues. Thus Supply, a quantity of things which
are sold, and Demand, a quantity of things which are bought, together determine
Price, a quantity of money; when Supply and Demand marry on a particular point
of the diagram, they give birth to Equilibrium Price, which corresponds to a
universal state of bliss. The activities of everyday life are played out by
things, and people are reduced to things ("factors of production") during their
productive" hours, and to passive spectators of things during their "leisure
time." The virtue of the Economic Scientist consists of his ability to attribute
the outcome of people's everyday activities to things, and of his inability
to see the living activity of people underneath the antics of the things. For
the Economist, the things through which the activity of people is regulated
under capitalism are themselves the mothers and sons, the causes and consequences
of their own activity.
The magnitude of value, namely the price of a commodity, the quantity of money
for which it exchanges, is not determined by things, but by the daily activities
of people. Supply and demand, perfect and imperfect competition, are nothing
more than social forms of products and activities in capitalist society; they
have no life of their own. The fact that activity is alienated, namely that
labor-time is sold for a specific sum of money, that it has a certain value,
has several consequences for the magnitude of the value of the products of that
labor. The value of the sold commodities must at least be equal to the value
of the labor-time. This is obvious both from the standpoint of the individual
capitalist firm, and from the standpoint of society as a whole. If the value
of the commodities sold by the individual capitalist were smaller than the value
of the labor he hired, then his labor expenditures alone would be larger than
his earnings, and he would quickly go bankrupt. Socially, if the value of the
laborers production were smaller than the value of their consumption, then the
labor force could not even reproduce itself, not to speak of a class of capitalists.
However, if the value of the commodities were merely equal to the value of the
labor- time expended on them, the commodity producers would merely reproduce
themselves, and their society would not be a capitalist society; their activity
might still consist of commodity production, but it would not be capitalist
commodity production.
For labor to create Capital, the value of the products of labor must be larger
than the value of the labor. In other words, the labor force must produce a
surplus product, a quantity of goods which it does not consume, and this surplus
product must be transformed into surplus value, a form of value which is not
appropriated by workers as wages, but by capitalists as profit. Furthermore,
the value of the products of labor must be larger still, since living labor
is not the only kind of labor materialized in them. In the production process,
workers expend their own energy, but they also use up the stored labor of others
as instruments, and they shape materials on which labor was previously expended.
This leads to the strange result that the value of the laborer's products and
the value of his wage are different magnitudes, namely that the sum of money
received by the capitalist when he sells the commodities produced by his hired
laborers is different from the sum he pays the laborers. This difference is
not explained by the fact that the used- up materials and tools must be paid
for. If the value of the sold commodities were equal to the value of the living
labor and the instruments, there would still be no room for capitalists. The
fact is that the difference between the two magnitudes must be large enough
to support a class of capitalists-not only the individuals, but also the specific
activity that these individuals engage in, namely the purchase of labor. The
difference between the total value of the products and the value of the labor
spent on their production is surplus value, the seed of Capital.
In order to locate the origin of surplus value, it is necessary to examine why
the value of the labor is smaller than the value of the commodities produced
by it. The alienated activity of the worker transforms materials with the aid
of instruments, and produces a certain quantity of commodities. However, when
these commodities are sold and the used-up materials and instruments are paid
for, the workers are not given the remaining value of their products as their
wages; they are given less. In other words, during every working day, the workers
perform a certain quantity of unpaid labor, forced label, for which they receive
no equivalent.
The performance of this unpaid labor, this forced labor, is another "condition
for survival" in capitalist society. However, like alienation, this condition
is not imposed by nature, but by the collective practice of people, by their
everyday activities. Before the existence of unions, an individual worker accepted
whatever forced labor was available, since rejection of the labor would have
meant that other workers would accept the available terms of exchange, and the
individual worker would receive no wage. Workers competed with each other for
the wages offered by capitalists; if a worker quit because the wage was unacceptably
low, an unemployed worker was willing to replace him, since for the unemployed
a small wage is higher than no wage at all. This competition among workers was
called "free labor" by capitalists, who made great sacrifices to maintain the
freedom of workers, since it was precisely this freedom that preserved the surplus
value of the capitalist and made it possible for him to accumulate Capital.
It was not any worker's aim to produce more goods than he was paid for. His
aim was to get a wage which was as large as possible. However, the existence
of workers who got no wage at all, and whose conception of a large wage was
consequently more modest than that of an employed worker, made it possible for
the capitalist to hire labor at a lower wage. In fact, the existence of unemployed
workers made it possible for the capitalist to pay the lowest wage that workers
were willing to work for. Thus the result of the collective daily activity of
the workers, each striving individually for the largest possible wage, was to
lower the wages of all; the effect of the competition of each against all was
that all got the smallest possible wage, and the capitalist got the largest
possible surplus.
The daily practice of all annuls the goals of each. But the workers did not
know that their situation was a product of their own daily behavior; their own
activities were not transparent to them. To the workers it seemed that low wages
were simply a natural part of life, like illness and death, and that falling
wages were a natural catastrophe, like a flood or a hard winter. The critiques
of socialists and the analyses of Marx, as well as an increase in industrial
development which afforded more time for reflection, stripped away some of the
veils and made it possible for workers to see through their activities to some
extent. However. in Western Europe and the United States, workers did not get
rid of the capitalist form of daily life; they formed unions. And in the different
material conditions of the Soviet Union and Eastern Europe, workers (and peasants)
replaced the capitalist class with a state bureaucracy that purchases alienated
labor and accumulates Capital in the name of Marx.
With unions, daily life is similar to what it was before unions. in fact, it
is almost the same. Daily life continues to consist of labor, of alienated activity,
and of unpaid labor, or forced labor. The unionized worker no longer settles
the terms of his alienation; union functionaries do this for him. The terms
on which the worker's activity is alienated are no longer guided by the individual
worker's need to accept what is available; they are now guided by the union
bureaucrat's need to maintain his position as pimp between the sellers of labor
and the buyers.
With or without unions, surplus value is neither a product of nature nor of
Capital; it is created by the daily activities of people. In the performance
of their daily activities, people are not only disposed to alienate these activities,
they are also disposed to reproduce the conditions which force them to alienate
their activities, to reproduce Capital and thus the power of Capital to purchase
labor. This is not because they do not know "what the alternative is." A person
who is incapacitated by chronic indigestion because he eats ton much grease
does not continue eating grease because he does not know what the alternative
is. Either he prefers being incapacitated to giving up grease, or else it is
not clear to him that his daily consumption of grease causes his incapacity.
And if his doctor, preacher, teacher and politician tell him, first, that the
grease is what keeps him alive, and secondly that they already do for him everything
he would do if he were well, then it is not surprising that his activity is
not transparent to him and that he makes no great effort to render it transparent.
The production of surplus value is a condition of survival, not for the population,
but for the capitalist system Surplus value is the portion of the value of commodities
produced by labor which is not returned to the laborers. It can be expressed
either in commodities or in money (just as Capital can be expressed either as
a quantity things or of money), but this does not alter the fact that it is
an expression for the materialized labor which is stored in a given quantity
of products. Since the products can be exchanged for an "equivalent" quantity
of money, the money "stands for", or represents, the same value as the products.
The money can, in turn, be exchanged for another quantity of products of "equivalent"
value. The ensemble of these exchanges, which take place simultaneously during
the performance of capitalist daily life, constitutes the capitalist process
of circulation. It is through this process that the metamorphosis of surplus
value into Capital takes place.
The portion of value which does not return to labor, namely surplus value, allows
the capitalist to exist, and it also allows him to do much more than simply
exist. The capitalist invests a portion of this surplus value; he hires new
workers and buys new means of production; he expands his dominion. What this
means is that the capitalist accumulates new labor, both in the form of the
living labor he hires and of the past labor (paid and unpaid) which is stored
in the materials and machines he buys.
The capitalist class as a whole accumulates the surplus labor of society, but
this process takes place on a social scale and consequently cannot be seen if
one observes only the activities of an individual capitalist. It must be remembered
that the products bought by a given capitalist as instruments have the same
characteristics as the products he sells. A first capitalist sells instruments
to a second capitalist for a given sum of value, and only a part of this value
is returned to workers as wages; the remaining part is surplus value, with which
the first capitalist buys new instruments and labor. The second capitalist buys
the instruments for the given value, which means that he pays for the total
quantity of labor rendered to the first capitalist, the quantity of labor which
was remunerated as well as the quantity performed free of charge. This means
that the instruments accumulated by the second capitalist contain the unpaid
labor performed for the first. The second capitalist, in turn, sells his products
for a given value, and returns only a portion of this value to his laborers;
he uses the remainder for new instruments and labor.
If the whole process were squeezed into a single time period, and if all the
capitalists were aggregated into one, it would he seen that the value with which
the capitalist acquires new instruments and labor is equal to the value of the
products which he did not return to the producers. This accumulated surplus
labor is Capital.
In terms of capitalist society as a whole, the total Capital is equal to the
sum of unpaid labor performed by generations of human beings whose lives consisted
of the daily alienation of their living activity. In other words Capital, in
the face of which men sell their living days, is the product of the sold activity
of men, and is reproduced and expanded every day a man sells another working
day, every moment he decides to continue living the capitalist form of daily
life.
Storage and Accumulation of Human Activity
The transformation of surplus labor into Capital is a specific historical form
of a more general process, the process of industrialization, the permanent transformation
of man's material environment.
Certain essential characteristics of this consequence of human activity under
capitalism can he grasped by means of a simplified illustration. In an imaginary
society, people spend most of their active time producing food and other necessities;
only part of their time is "surplus time" in the sense that it is exempted from
the production of necessities. This surplus activity may be devoted to the production
of food for priests and warriors who do not themselves produce; it may be used
to produce goods which are burned for sacred occasions; it may be used up in
the performance of ceremonies or gymnastic exercises. In any of these cases,
the material conditions of these people are not likely to change, from one generation
to another, as a result of their daily activities. However, one generation of
people of this imaginary society may store their surplus time instead of using
it up. For example, they may spend this surplus time winding up springs. The
next generation may unwind the energy stored in the springs to perform necessary
tasks, or may simply use the energy of the springs to wind new springs. In either
case, the stored surplus labor of the earlier generation will provide the new
generation with a larger quantity of surplus working time. The new generation
may also store this surplus in springs and in other receptacles. In a relatively
short period, the labor stored in the springs will exceed the labor time available
to any living generation; with the expenditure of relatively little energy,
the people of this imaginary society will be able to harness the springs to
most of their necessary tasks, and also to the task of winding new springs for
coming generations. Most of the living hours which they previously spent producing
necessities will now be available for activities which are not dictated by necessity
but projected by the imagination.
At first glance it seems unlikely that people would devote living hours to the
bizarre task of winding springs. It seems just as unlikely, even if they wound
the springs, that they would store them for future generations, since the unwinding
of the springs might provide, for example, a marvellous spectacle on festive
days.
However, if people did not dispose of their own lives, if their working activity
were not their own, if their practical activity consisted of forced labor, then
human activity might well be harnessed to the task of winding springs, the task
of storing surplus working time in material receptacles. The historical role
of Capitalism, a role which was performed by people who accepted the legitimacy
of others to dispose of their lives, consisted precisely of storing human activity
in material receptacles by means of forced labor.
As soon as people submit to the "power" of money to buy stored labor as well
as living activity, as soon as they accept the fictional "right" of money-holders
to control and dispose of the stored as well as the living activity of society,
they transform money into Capital and the owners of money into Capitalists.
This double alienation, the alienation of living activity in the form of wage
labor, and the alienation of the activity of past generations in the form of
stored labor (means of production), is not a single act which took place sometime
in history. The relation between workers and capitalists is not a thing which
imposed itself on society at some point in the past, once and for all. At no
time did men sign a contract, or even make a verbal agreement, in which they
gave up the power over their living activity, and in which they gave up the
power over the living activity of all future generations on all parts of the
globe.
Capital wears the mask of a natural force; it seems as solid as the earth itself;
its movements appear as irreversible as tides; its crises seem as unavoidable
as earthquakes and floods. Even when it is admitted that the power of Capital
is created by men, this admission may merely be the occasion for the invention
of an even more imposing mask, the mask of a man-made force, a Frankenstein
monster, whose power inspires more awe than that of any natural force.
However, Capital is neither a natural force nor a man- made monster which was
created sometime in the past and which dominated human life ever since. The
power of Capital does not reside in money, since money is a social convention
which has no more "power" than men are willing to grant it; when men refuse
to sell their labor, money cannot perform even the simplest tasks, because money
does not "work."
Nor does the power of Capital reside in the material receptacles in which the
labor of past generations is stored, since the potential energy stored in these
receptacles can be liberated by the activity of living people whether or not
the receptacles are Capital, namely alien property." Without living activity,
the collection of objects which constitute society's Capital would merely be
a scattered heap of assorted artefacts with no life of their own, and the "owners''
of Capital would merely be a scattered assortment of uncommonly uncreative people
(by training) who surround themselves with bits of paper in a vain attempt to
resuscitate memories of past grandeur. The only "power" of Capital resides in
the daily activities of living people; this "power" consists of the disposition
of people to sell their daily activities in exchange for money, and to give
up control over the products of their own activity and of the activity of earlier
generations.
As soon as a person sells his labor to a capitalist and accepts only a part
of his product as payment for that labor, he creates conditions for the purchase
and exploitation of other people. No man would willingly give his arm or his
child in exchange for money; yet when a man deliberately and consciously sells
his working life in order to acquire the necessities for life, he not only reproduces
the conditions which continue to make the sale of his life a necessity for its
preservation; he also creates conditions which make the sale of life a necessity
for other people. Later generations may of course refuse to sell their working
lives for the same reason that he refused to sell his arm; however each failure
to refuse alienated and forced labor enlarges the stock of stored labor with
which Capital can buy working lives.
In order to transform surplus labor into Capital, the capitalist has to find
a way to store it in material receptacles, in new means of production. and he
must hire new laborers to activate the new means of production. In other words,
he must enlarge his enterprise, or start a new enterprise in a different branch
of production. This presupposes or requires the existence of materials that
can be shaped into new saleable commodities, the existence of buyers of the
new products, and the existence of people who are poor enough to be willing
to sell their labor. These requirements are themselves created by capitalist
activity, and capitalists recognize no limits or obstacles to their activity;
the democracy of Capital demands absolute freedom.
Imperialism is not merely the "last stage" of Capitalism; it is also the first.
Anything which can be transformed into a marketable good is grist for Capital's
mill, whether it lies on the capitalist's land or on the neighbor's, whether
it lies above ground or under, Boats on the sea or crawls on its floor; whether
it is confined to other continents or other planets. All of humanity's explorations
of nature, from Alchemy to Physics, are mobilized to search for new materials
in which to store labor, to find new objects that someone can be taught to buy.
Buyers for old and new products are created by any and all available means,
and new means are constantly discovered. "Open markets" and "open doors" are
established by force and fraud. If people lack the means to buy the capitalists'
products, they are hired by capitalists and are paid for producing the goods
they wish to buy; if local craftsmen already produce what the capitalists have
to sell, the craftsmen are ruined or bought-out; if laws or traditions ban the
use of certain products, the laws and the traditions are destroyed; if people
lack the objects on which to use the capitalists' products, they are taught
to buy these objects; if people run out of physical or biological wants, then
capitalists "satisfy" their "spiritual wants" and hire psychologists to create
them; if people are so satiated with the products of capitalists that they can
no longer use new objects, they are taught to buy objects and spectacles which
have no use but can simply be observed and admired.
Poor people are found in pre-agrarian and agrarian societies on every continent;
if they are not poor enough to be willing to sell their labor when the capitalists
arrive, they are impoverished by the activities of the capitalists themselves.
The lands of hunters gradually become the "private property" of "owners" who
use state violence to restrict the hunters to "reservations" which do not contain
enough food to keep them alive. The tools of peasants gradually become available
only from the same merchant who generously lends them the money with which to
buy the tools, until the peasants' "debts" are so large that they are forced
to sell land which neither they nor any of their ancestors had ever bought.
The buyers of craftsmen's products gradually become reduced to the merchants
who market the products, until the day comes when a merchant decides to house
"his craftsmen" under the same roof, and provides them with the instruments
which will enable all of them to concentrate their activity on the production
of the most profitable items. Independent as well as dependent hunters, peasants
and craftsmen, free men as well as slaves, are transformed into hired laborers.
Those who previously disposed of their own lives in the face of harsh material
conditions cease to dispose of their own lives precisely when they take up the
task of modifying their material conditions; those who were previously conscious
creators of their own meagre existence become unconscious victims of their own
activity even while abolishing the meagreness of their existence. Men who were
much but had little now have much but are little.
The production of new commodities, the "opening" of new markets, the creation
of new workers, are not three separate activities; they are three aspects of
the same activity. A new labor force is created precisely in order to produce
the new commodities; the wages received by these laborers are themselves the
new market; their unpaid labor is the source of new expansion. Neither natural
nor cultural barriers halt the spread of Capital, the transformation of people's
daily activity into alienated labor, the transformation of their surplus labor
into the "private property" of capitalists. However, Capital is not a natural
force; it is a set of activities performed by people every day; it is a form
of daily life; its continued existence and expansion presuppose only one essential
condition: the disposition of people to continue to alienate their working lives
and thus reproduce the capitalist form of daily life.
Reprinted in 'Anything Can Happen', October 1992, Phoenix Press, London,
which also contains Perlman's 'The Continuing
Appeal of Nationalism'